ALEX PREDA
We see
ourselves as small shareholders, as critical shareholders, as shareholders of
ethical businesses, or of venture firms. We are against grand speculators, or
dream of becoming one someday; we follow price movements every day, or only now
and then, trade online, or go to a trusted broker, watch the news, look at
price charts, discuss the market with friends, and so much more. Contemporary
capitalism would not be the same without the investor. Against this background,
it is surprising that we still lack a sociological analysis. How does this
figure work and to what consequences? Its substantial presence and broad societal
impact suggest that it is not a new phenomenon, but rather the outcome of a
historical process. Since its public prominence is tied to the second
globalization wave (the increased worldwide integration of capital markets
since the 1980s), an adequate strategy of inquiry would be to investigate its
shape in the first globalization wave (the period between 1850 and 1914, when
capital markets witnessed a comparable level of integration). Concomitantly,
the figure of the investor raises some crucial questions for the sociology of
financial markets concerning the ways in which structural conditions are
related to agency, economic action is shaped by cultural factors, and the
categories of economic order translate into categories of individual experience.
I make here two arguments:
the theoretical one is that the sociological concept of figure is a useful
tool for analyzing how financial markets generate valid, socially legitimate
types of social actors. The empirical argument is that in the first globalization
wave (1850—1914)1 the investor is reconfigured as having universal
validity and as legitimating market globalization. I single out two
interrelated aspects of this reconfiguration: (a) the transformation of the
investor into a scientist bound to discover the universal laws of the markets
and (b) the notion that investing is intrinsic to human nature and a basic
social right. I begin my examination by developing the sociological concept of
figure. I show then that the sociological tradition identifies four basic
This
chapter has very much benefitted from the comments of Karin Knorr Cetina,
Barbara Grimpe, Aaron Pitluck, and Peimaneh Riahi. My thanks to them all.
figures
of capitalism: (1) the manufacturer, (2) the entrepreneur, (3) the accumulating
capitalist, and (4) the religious capitalist. The missing figure here is that
of the investor. In the next step I examine the reconfiguration of the investor
along two lines: (a) the investor-scientist and (b) the right to invest. This
reconfiguration occurs during the first globalization wave and marks a rupture
with the eighteenth century figure of the investor. I show how (a) and (b)
contribute to creating a cultural figure with universal validity, which
legitimates global market expansion.
I rely in this examination
on primary sources from the United States, United Kingdom, and France from
1850-1914. For comparison, I will also draw on primary sources from eighteenth
century Britain and France (in the United States, institutionalized financial
markets started around 1792). I refer here to investment books, magazines,
newspaper articles, and reminiscences of investors; my arguments are grounded
in the examination of over four hundred original documents directly related to
and produced in investment activities. My method is that of an analytical
reconstruction of the figure of the investor as constituted in the cultural
field of investment activities (specified in the fourth section on ‘The Figure
of the Investor in the Eighteenth Century’).
The
investor as a figure of capitalism: is he or she then an abstraction, a
fictionalized portrait of historical figures? We can easily imagine a fictionalized
amalgamation of ‘grand speculators’, Jay Gould and Cornelius Vanderbilt mixed
up with Carl Icahn and Warren Buffett. But is it not defining for these grand
figures that they live through hyperbole, through countless stories about their
exploits? And what about those investors who are absent from such stories? An
amalgamation of historic characters would describe the grand figure rather than
explain it. Shall we then understand the investor as a trope, a figure in the
discourse of capitalism, a justification for engagement with financial markets,
one which went beyond (uncertain) profit? This is intrinsic to the figure of
the investor; yet, justification alone cannot bring unrelated actors to engage
in similar paths of action, cannot completely explain how social responsibility
is placed on them. There is more to the figure of the investor than
justification.
If
neither a fictional character, nor a trope, then what is the figure of the
investor? Generally speaking, we encounter at least three meanings of the concept
of the figure: (1) In rhetoric, the figure (of speech) or the trope designates
a displacement of linguistic meaning, which takes place according to established
rules of communication and is embedded in a pattern of persuasive argument.
Thus, metaphors, litotes, or allegories as figures of speech are rule-governed
elements of persuasive communication. (2) In literary studies, the figure
designates a character in a novel or play, with the following properties: (a)
placement in space and time; (b) development; (c) mimesis—that is, imitation of
a person or class of persons from real life; (d) involvement in a pattern of
action; (e) embeddedness in a web of relationships. (3) By opposition, the
sociological concept of figure stresses neither exclusively linguistic aspects
nor mimetic character. Note that the notion of figure does not entirely overlap
with the sociological concept of role. While the latter is understood as a
behavioral script which reflects social-structural constraints at the
individual level, the figure implies the reciprocal adaptation between broad
cultural categories, on the one hand, and categories of individual experience,
on the other. The outcome of this process is a set of dispositions shaping
individual paths of action. The concept of figure is grounded in a series of
arguments which include, among others, Gabriel Tarde’s examination of the
economic act, Erving Goffman’s analysis of the interaction order, and Norbert
Elias’ and Pierre Bourdieu’s notions of figuration and figure, respectively.
There
are two basic premises to this concept: the first is that the self cannot be
constituted through solipsistic acts (i.e. pertaining exclusively to one’s own
character or private ego) but emerges in the interaction order. Thus, agency
implies an interplay of forces, a system of different positions, roles, and
performances on the part of social actors. An important argument in this sense
is formulated by Gabriel Tarde: for him, the broader economic order requires a
correlate at the individual level. The institutional categories of economic
life need individual acts as a correlate, otherwise there would be no economy
out there. These individual acts are grounded in beliefs; belief, however, is
not a category of individual psychology, but of social interaction. The
economic self is constituted at the level of the interaction order: none of her
acts can be purely individual. Economic acts will always be coconstituted by
interaction elements like commonly held values, moral projections, and
collective representations (including fears, exuberance, and the like) (Tarde
1902: 290). Tarde’s arguments resonate with Erving Goffman’s. Goffman (in a
larger context) sees the self as constituted by situated rules of interaction
in the same way in which a theater figure is constituted on a stage in the
interaction with coplayers (1959: 30-31). Since the interaction order is a sui-
generis one (irreducible to individual psychological elements, or to biological
determinants), it becomes necessary to analyze the process-like constitution of
social selves and of the categories in which the social world is experienced.
Norbert Elias formulates a related argument, in that he sees agency (a) as
depending on the constitution of the self and (b) on the interaction between
selves. Elias’ case study is that of the European court societies at the dawn
of the modern era. Court societies were intricate webs of social positions,
roles, and forces, in which individual selves (i.e. of the king, the nobleman,
the court lady) were shaped by the rule-determined interaction process. The
self is then not an isolated creation, but a figure situated in a web of
interactions in which other figures exert their forces. The concept of figure
designates then the interplay between structure and individual agency in an
interaction web. Figuration is the process through which individual selves and
macrosocial processes are tied to each other: it ensures that social facts are
created concomitantly on the collective and on the individual level (Elias
1983 [1969]: 21, 208-9).
This brings us to the
second conceptual premise, namely that structural elements have to be matched
by categories of experience on the part of individual actors. Without this
match social actors cannot be explained but as robots. Paths of social action
(and categories of experience with them), however, are not identical, but
similar. Pierre Bourdieu explains (dis)similarities between these paths as
being due to the position they occupy in the (literary) field (1996: 129, 132).
During the Second Empire in France, for example, we do not encounter a single,
homogenous figure of the literate, but several: the bohemian intellectual, the
public intellectual, the popular writer, the social critic. These figures are
situated in a field of cultural differences, according to the categories in
which they experience the social world, to the social and cultural capital
they dispose of, and to the resources they can mobilize. At the same time,
external forces are exerted upon the literary field: for example, by the
bourgeoisie who tolerates (or even sponsors) the bohemian, or by the political
class. The consequences are that the notion of figure is neither a mechanical
translation of structural constraints at the individual level nor reduced to a
single set of determinants (economic or political). Figures shape the field
(i.e. the structural conditions) in which they act.
In the
sociological tradition, we encounter a continuous preoccupation with the
figures generated by the modern capitalist order: the expert, the public man,
the consumer, the intellectual are only some major examples. Among the attempts
to define capitalism by the figures it generates, at least the following
categories figure prominently: (1) the manufacturer, (2) the entrepreneur, (3)
the accumulating capitalist, and (4) the religious capitalist. Adam Smith’s
manufacturer and Joseph Schumpeter’s entrepreneur belong to (1) and (2),
respectively. Karl Marx’s and Max Weber’s respective figures of capitalists are
examples of (3) and (4). Their authors saw these figures not as byproducts, but
as key with respect to the capitalist order: they are the individual
counterpart and the source of the entity called capital.
In the eighteenth century,
‘capitalist’ was understood by social philosophers, by economic thinkers, and
by the educated public alike as a person who invests money in public debt or in
stock, and expects an annuity or a dividend. A capitalist was someone who did
not have to work for a living, nor lived off land revenue, nor had profits from
manufacture or trade. His revenue was derived from the financial securities he
owned and traded. At the dawn of the modern era, being a capitalist meant being
an investor (DuPlessis 2002: 36). Only toward the end of the century did Adam
Smith’s (1991) Wealth of Nations give a new, abstract twist to the term
‘capitalist’.
A superficial observer may
say that Adam Smith has not depicted a central figure of capitalism, being too
busy with the grand tableau of the national economy. Yet, Smith’s economic
landscape is not an empty one, but populated by a whole array of figures, some
of which are of central importance. Increasing the nation’s wealth is, in Adam
Smith’s eyes, the ultimate aim of economic life. While agriculture, trade, and
other economic activities may contribute to wealth increase, great nations
excel in manufacturing (Smith 1991 [1776]: 12). All other economic
activities—like banking and trade—are subordinated to increasing the
manufacture industry of the country (p. 258). The manufacturer is skilled and innovative:
he has a deep knowledge of production processes and of local conditions, is
geared toward permanent productivity improvements, and is interested in
long-term development. Of all social types, wrote Smith, the ‘master
manufacturer’ plays the central role; the merchant, another important figure,
is subordinated to the manufacturer in the social order of wealth.
Manufacturers have the best knowledge of their own interest, a self-interest
which is the very spirit of capitalism: ‘during their whole lives (they) are
engaged in plans and projects, they have frequently more acuteness of
understanding than the country gentlemen... Their superiority over the country
gentleman is not so much in their knowledge of the public interest, as in
having a better knowledge of their own interest than he has of his’ (p. 219).
Analogously, Schumpeter’s
entrepreneur (1934) is motivated by a constant, almost religious drive for
(technical) innovation. In this respect, the entrepreneur combines Adam Smith’s
manufacturer with Max Weber’s charisma. Capitalism is characterized by a ‘habit
of mind’: that of striving toward technical innovation for economic profit.
Innovation is the motor of economic growth and capitalist expansion. The
entrepreneur is its major figure. He is not merely interested in science and
technology for their own sake; he is interested in continuous innovation
because he equates it with economic advantage. Innovations solve major economic
uncertainties and set the stage for imitators. Technical and economic processes
are closely related to each other; technology is endogenous to the capitalist
economic system (Rosenberg 2000: 12). The entrepreneur is different both from
the manager and the ‘capitalist risk-taker’ (i.e. the investor) (Schumpeter
1991: 407-8). He invents or innovates as a response to economic and social
pressures and, in doing this, he promotes economic change. At the same time,
Schumpeter’s entrepreneur remains separate and independent from the investor;
he may put his talents in the service of joint-stock companies, but financial
speculation is not his defining feature (1991: 425 n4, n9).
In the
introduction to the first edition of the Capital, Karl Marx stated clearly that the figure of
the capitalist was the ‘personification of economic categories, bearer of class
relationships and interests’ (2002 [1872]: 37). Relevant here is the fact that
in the Capital, this figure is determined
by the process of accumulation.
For Marx, capitalism is
reducible to two key aspects: the worker selling his labor force to the
capitalist, and the capitalist being able to obtain surplus value by paying not
for the labor, but for the reproduction of the labor force. Hence, the key
relationship of capitalism is that between the capitalist and the worker: while
the former accumulates, the latter sells his only possession. For the
capitalist, the main type of social action is accumulation; for the worker, it
is selling his labor force. Accumulation is a purely economic process, free of
any ethical determinations. He who accumulates does not need to sell his labor
force, and he who has to sell it all the time cannot accumulate. These two
kinds of complementary actions are paradigmatic for capitalism and for the
relationship between these two figures. Capitalism as a social order depends on
the relationship between accumulation and the sale of labor force. Marx’s
entire analysis is geared toward deducing the laws of capitalism out of this
relationship.
While
Marx’s capitalist accumulation is free of ethical determinations, Max Weber saw
the capitalist as a religiously motivated man: his drive toward redemption
justifies getting rich as a self-contained aim. Since redemption is uncertain,
all that is left is hope, which is supported by a constant strive toward
accumulating riches. Accumulation, however, has to obey certain rules: the
virtuous capitalist accumulates by his own ingenuity, frugality, sustained
work, and constant preoccupation with economic processes. Religious asceticism
forbids accumulation by speculation (Weber 1988 [1920]: 191). While witnessing
waves of financial speculation in Germany, Weber did not really view financial
markets as being at the core of the capitalist order. The most he could do
about them was to write a popularizing brochure (Weber 2000 [1894]). Continuous
work and profit through production (Weber 1988 [1920]: 175) are the legitimate
means of religious salvation.
These
figures are not mere traces in the history of political economy. Historically
seen, they may coexist; from the conceptual point of view, however, each
claims primacy in explanatory accounts of capitalism.
Manufacturer,
entrepreneur, accumulating capitalist, religious capitalist: some of them are
easy to recognize in today’s global capitalism. For instance, the figure of the
dot.com entrepreneur was familiar and much cherished in the late 1990s. Other
figures may be paler now than one hundred years ago. Nevertheless, striking in
this enumeration is the fact that none of these figures is directly related to
a fundamental institution of capitalism: financial markets. They are involved
in production processes, in manufacture and technology; trade may play here a
role too. Financial markets, however, are a notable absence. Of course, Adam
Smith was aware of the merchant’s role; but the merchant is subordinated to the
manufacturer and is not involved in financial markets. In fact, Adam Smith did
not consider these latter to contribute to national wealth; he saw financial
markets as a noneconomic domain, a view clearly expressed in the last chapter
of the Wealth
of Nations (1991 [1776]: 534).
Yet
economic opinion has radically changed: contemporary economic historians see
financial markets—from the moment when they emerged—not as a mere byproduct of
capitalism, but as its very motor (Sylla 1999a, b). This change of opinion goes
hand in hand with the belief—rooted in eighteenth century illuminist
thinking—that the market generates a fundamentally new human type (Hirschman
1992: 109): ‘the archetype of capitalism is the shareholder who places his
money in an enterprise and expects a profit’ (Boltanski and Chiapello 1999:
39). Placing money, holding shares, expecting profit: all these actions,
attitudes, and expectations are intrinsically related to financial markets as the capitalist institution. As
early as 1901, Georg Simmel noticed that the stock exchange—characterized
through permanent movement and continuous excitement—is an ‘extreme increase in
the rhythm of life’ and the ‘point of the greatest excitement of economic life’
(Simmel 1989 [1901]: 708). If this is so, there must be a fifth, lost figure of
capitalism: the investor. Understanding the ‘spirit of capitalism’ cannot
ignore a figure tied to one of its core institutions, a figure which has
positioned herself at the very center of this order, one on which so many hopes
and responsibilities are placed and which has to take so many risks.
On the
one hand, the figure of the investor is tied to the paths of action followed by
so many unrelated actors: these actions cannot be seen as habit, as unreflected
routine; they cannot be seen as coerced, or as automatically induced by
education, income, social milieu, profession, and the like. They are similar or
complementary, yet not identical: obviously, not everybody buys the same
security at the same time. Thus, the figure of the investor should take these
paths of action into account and show how they relate to the legitimacy of
markets.
On the
other hand, the figure of the investor is tied to the legitimacy of capitalist
order: being an investor has to do with the social legitimacy of financial
markets, with how enterprises are organized and property relations are
structured. Among others, the investor is central for how relations of
ownership are organized in capitalism, for how firms are conceived. This
implies not only the right and the ability to own shares, but also to trade
them, actively intervening on the market. The assumptions underlying this
organization of ownership go well beyond the sphere of economic concepts: we
own some part (however minuscule) of a corporation, we hold and trade
securities not only because it is economically profitable (for this is
uncertain), but also because it is socially and morally justified, because we
accept this arrangement as legitimate. In short, the figure of the investor has
to do with capitalism as a justified and just order (Boltanski and Thevenot 1991:
59).
This
means taking into account the ‘sets of beliefs associated with the capitalist
order, which contribute to justify this order and to support, through
legitimating, the modes of action and the dispositions coherent with capitalism’
(Boltanski and Chiapello 1999: 46). Hence, we have to explain the bind between
beliefs in the social and moral legitimacy of investments, and action
categories which confirm and reinforce these beliefs. Belief in the social
legitimacy of investments cannot be conflated with belief in their economic
profitability. They are apparently flexible and multilayered enough to legitimate
the grand speculator and the small investor, the billionaire and the employee,
the day trader and the occasional buyer of treasury bills. As the recent
account of a sociologist and amateur investor puts it, the grand speculator
and the small investor, the full-time professional and the amateur alike belong
to an ‘imagined community’ of market actors (Pollner 2002: 231).
In the
same way, categories of social action cannot be limited to the financial
marketplace, to trading securities. One reason is that financial transactions
are tied to and dependent on larger categories of action: gathering
information, evaluation procedures, knowing transactions partners, and the
like. Another reason is that the notion of financial transaction, of investing
in financial securities already presupposes that of the investor: it will be
then a logical fallacy to reduce action categories to those of the marketplace.
A
further aspect is given by the material arrangements and devices related to the
categories of meaningful financial action. Gathering information, for example,
depends on communication devices, on the material support of information. At
the same time, devices and technologies can in themselves constitute paths of
action: an economic study may require from investors different actions than
economic gossip. Material devices play an important role in legitimating paths
of action as well as the larger social order in which they are embedded
(Mukerji 1997). They can make this legitimacy visible for several people at
once, symbolize the legitimate order, and corroborate discursive formulations
of this order. Consequently, we should not see the figure of the investor as
exclusively constituted by (discursive) beliefs and action categories. In
investigating this figure, we need to examine the configurations of mutually
supporting beliefs, action categories, and material arrangements (devices,
technical artifacts).
These configurations are
not straightjackets. They do not impose courses of action; they make them
possible, and make these possibilities inevitable. I argue here that the figure
of the investor is constituted in a configuration (or field) of discourses
about and of investing, material arrangements, and cognitive instruments. The
discourses about investing establish how investment activities are
conceptualized and represented; discourses of investing, related to activities,
establish the communication modes between financial actors. Material arrangements,
in their turn, determine the settings of investment activities, the quality of
financial information, and shape the interaction modes of investors. Cognitive
instruments determine how financial information is processed and by whom,
affecting the discourses of investing. The field of investing is not isolated
from the political, the technological, or the literary field; agency coming
from these fields can produce significant changes in the material arrangements
of investing activities or in their legitimacy.
There is
general agreement that investors are not a sudden, recent occurrence. There
have been investors since the emergence of financial markets in Amsterdam,
London, and Paris in the late seventeenth and early eighteenth century. While
we still lack a systematic, comprehensive quantitative examination of
investors in the eighteenth century, we possess descriptions of the financial
marketplaces of this time (e.g. Schama 1997 [1987]: 343-71) and partial
statistical analyses of company shareholders and of bondholders (e.g. Neal
1990; Carruthers 1996; Sylla 1998; Garber 2000; Wright 2001). The eighteenth
century is the century of periodic enthusiasm with investing and speculation,
of great periodic bubbles followed by periods of silence. The South Sea, the
Mississippi, the Compagnie des Eaux, the Banque Saint Charles, and the Wall
Street speculative manias have introduced a permanent notion into the
vocabulary of finance: the bubble. If historical descriptions are to be
believed, people from all social strata have participated in these speculative
frenzies. At the same time, the eighteenth century is the century of heavy
moral, economic, and political doubts about investing, of great anti-speculative
tides. These doubts concern the relationship between investing and gambling,
the effects of financial investing upon the character of the individual, upon
the productive forces of society, upon social classes and the state. At the
dusk of the century, the French revolution turned the tide against investing by
asking for the death penalty on any kind of financial speculation. Edward
Chancellor has recently argued that the culture of financial investments in the
eighteenth century was carnival-like, characterized by popular participation
coupled with ‘a Utopian yearning for freedom and economic equality’ (1999: 29).
The notion of carnival culture, however, does not fit well with the overall
deep skepticism about the social legitimacy of investments.
In the
eighteenth century, the dominant discourses about investment activities were
those of the moral pamphlet, comedy, satire, and visual allegory. The knowledge
on which investments were based was marked by folly, ‘the passion of avarice,
the disease of fools and earth-worms’ (Truth 1733: 13-14). Speculation is a ‘deadly
science, a most obscure and deluding game’ (Mirabeau 1785: 77). Financial
speculation is a ‘scandalous mechanick’which has no reality in itself; it is
bewitching, deadly, a perverted art which ‘computes people out of their
senses’ (Some Seasonable Considerations 1720: 9). It is a mystery, a ‘machine
of trade with unheard-of engines’; it is an ‘impenetrable artifice, poison
acting at distance’ (The Villainy 1701: 22). This small sample of metaphors,
echoed in numerous publications, puts financial knowledge (and investments) in
stark contrast with natural science and social philosophy, bound to discover
the laws of the universe and of social order, respectively. A knowledge which
is folly and ‘devilish mechanick’ can be integrated neither in the order of
nature nor in that of the larger society.
While
there are many descriptions of financial markets, we encounter throughout the
century merely a single work claiming to be a manual on ‘the Mystery and
Iniquity of Stock-Jobbing’: Thomas Mortimer’s Every Man His Own Broker, published in 1761 in
London and going through several editions. It had the declared aim of
persuading ‘the proprietors of our public funds to transact their own business;
to make them the managers of their own property: the only effectual method that
can be taken to reduce the great number of Stock-brokers; to diminish the
extensive operations of stockjobbing; and, in the end, to extirpate this
infamous practice, which ruins many capital merchants and tradesmen every year’
(Mortimer 1782 [1761]: xvi).
In the
eighteenth century, investing was largely identified with gambling and clearly
perceived as a noneconomic activity, which in no way can contribute to the
wealth of the nation. Personal enrichment may occur, but it is socially illegitimate.
Correspondingly, the discourses of investing were keyed as burlesque,
treachery, blackmailing, and fraud. A widely used means of popular moral
education were posters and illustrated brochures about wrecked lives. The prostitute,
the pregnant unmarried woman, the thief, the robber, the liar, the dishonest
merchant were among the usual figures. Crimes were told in lurid detail.
Immoral lives always ended tragically, as a deterrent to the reader. Yet, these
figures were not the only ones: the financial speculator, the gambler in
stocks, was a constant presence in this panoply and his fate was not better
than that of robbers (e.g. The Life of Jonathan Wild 1725; A Complete Narrative 1790).
Those who
speculate are guilty of the sin of covetousness, which leads to fraud; they are
disorderly, immoderate (The Fatal Consequences 1720: 8-10), degenerate, working against
the public interest, dishonest, in a state of drunkenness and exaltation
(Mirabeau 1787: 10, 19, 53). Stock trading is traffic by deception and cunning
and a pernicious commerce. Financial markets destroy social order by attracting
people from other professions into investments (Sur la proposition 1789: 8, 12). The public
interest is ‘screwed down’ by ‘the fraud, knavery, deceit and illusion’ of
financial speculation (The Anatomy 1719: 3-4).
Speculation
is a poison which slowly destroys the state and leads to nonpayment of debts,
which leads to disorder (Laporte 1789: 50). Financial speculation is a menace
for the individual as well as for the social order.
The
stage on which investors are encountered is the close universe of pubs, back
alleys, and gardens, where the general rules of interaction are suspended. The
communicative order of investing is predominantly oral: at the interaction
level, the financial marketplace is constituted as a two-tiered conversational
system requiring permanent agitation and presence. This conversational system,
well adapted to multiple markets (the rule at the time) ascribes well-defined
roles to investors, roles which require special ways of speaking and body
techniques. Investors dispose of multiple price lists, more often than not
forged. Forging whole issues of newspapers and staging political events for
investment purposes was not very rare. A good example here is the staging of
Napoleon’s death for speculation purposes in 1814, a case that I have analyzed
elsewhere (see for details Preda 2001). In this field, the typical investor
figures are the bull, the bear, the sharper, the pigeon, the projector, the
monkey, and the lame duck (see Figure 7.1). While some of these metaphors have
become a staple of today’s financial vocabulary, they do not
|
||||||||||||
|
||||||||||||
|
||||||||||||
|
||||||||||||
|
||||||||||||
|
anymore identify investor
figures in the way they did in the eighteenth century. One may still be bullish
or bearish, but without being subjected to the behavioral scripts implied by
these terms two centuries ago.
In the
mid-nineteenth century, under the impact of various social forces, the figure
of the investor was reconfigured. Among the forces playing an important role
here are railway engineers. Around 1845, construction and railway engineers
became involved in railway economics and elaborated mathematical models of the
demand and supply functions for railway transportation. While thus
revolutionizing microeconomics (Ekelund and Hebert 1999: 54-5), engineers were
responsible both for technical and economic aspects of railway companies, being
involved in the evaluation of railway securities and their marketing to the
public. We encounter examples of railway engineering treatises from the 1850s
which discuss methods to evaluate railway securities and to speculate in them
(Lardner 1850: 310). Engineers transfer the vocabulary of physics to the
valuation of railway securities. They require observation and analysis in this
process. Sheer luck or emotions are seen as irrelevant. The vocabulary of
natural science replaces that of the moral pamphlet as the medium for representing
financial investments.
This
replacement is accompanied by the notion that financial markets are not
governed by whims, emotions, or intrigues, but by objective laws. Discovering
them is at the core of the efforts made by some stockbrokers in the same
period. A prominent example in this respect is Emile Regnault’s Chance Calculus and the
Philosophy of the Stock Exchange (1863), which formulates for the first
time the random walk hypothesis, crucial for the future development of
mathematical finance (Jovanovic and Le Gall 2001; Preda
2004) . Regnault argues that
speculation should follow the example of physics and discover the objective
laws which govern the market. True speculation must examine and know the
constant laws of stock price variations; these laws are as universal as the
gravitation laws (Regnault 1863: 143-4). No market actor can influence price
variations in the long run since these obey to ‘superior and providential laws’
(p. 185). His contribution was two ‘laws of differences’, according to which
(1) the differences between real and probable prices are a function of the
square root of time and (2) prices tend toward the median value of this
difference (p. 187). Regnault’s work was followed by Henri Lefevre’s (1870),
another stockbroker who catered to individual, nonprofessional investors.
Lefevre developed a graphic method for pricing derivatives; he started a
mutual fund (the Union Financiere) and devised a plan for national financial
education; he invented a mechanical device for pricing derivatives (the
auto-compteur), to be used on the floor of the stock exchange (see Preda 2004
for details). His graphic method was modified by Louis Bachelier (1964 [1900])
in his mathematical treatment of derivatives prices, which grounded the random
walk hypothesis.
We
should not underestimate the importance of the notion that financial markets
are governed by objective, probabilistic laws, and not by a group of
speculators. This notion relies on the assumption that large numbers of actors
are present in the market, so that nobody can control it in the long run. It
also purports to develop instruments for intervention in the market (e.g. for
pricing financial derivatives). This implies not only describing, but changing
the ways in which markets operate—a phenomenon analyzed by Donald MacKenzie and
Yuval Millo (2003) as performativity. It should be stressed here again that
these were investment manuals which did not address academic economists but
investors. Developments crucial for derivatives markets and for financial
economics were thus initiated in the mid-nineteenth century in the attempt to
transform investors into scientists bound to discover the hidden, objective
laws of financial investments.
The
science of investing contributed to disentangling investments from gambling.
The transformation of gambling into a medical condition (Brenner and Brenner
1990: 72-6), as well as the formal, probabilistic treatment of gambling
problems (Bernstein 1996)—which occurred independently of medicalization—also
played a part in this process. This new representation mode, disseminated by
numerous investment manuals, stressed careful observation and analysis. It
presented financial behavior as dispassionate, calm, grounded in permanent
observation of market events and in problem solving (e.g. Castelli 1877; Notions generales 1877: 62-4).
Developments
in price-recording technologies reinforced these demands. Until the late 1860s,
prices were recorded on paper slips and circulated by courier boys (Downey
2000: 132-3). Multiple markets with multiple prices coexisted in the same
building (Vidal 1910: 37-8; Walker 2001: 192-3). In 1867, telegraph engineers
developed and introduced the stock ticker to Wall Street; in less than two
decades, the ticker became a permanent fixture of Wall Street and of brokerage
houses, as well as of the London Stock Exchange. One of the effects of the
ticker was that it transformed parallel, sequential price information (as recorded
on paper slips) into a continuous flow (Preda 2002). This flow demanded
uninterrupted personal attention and observation on the part of investors.
Since they had to react quicker to financial information, investors had to
adopt artificial languages, exclusively expressing financial information.
Telegraph companies edited and disseminated extensive code books for
communicating this information. I will give here only two such examples: the
first comes from Hartfield’s Wall Street Code (1905) which contained
over 450,000 cypher words. An investor would then telegraph his broker
‘gabbiola baissabaci’ instead of ‘are you able to buy hundred shares?’ Those
using the manual of the Haight & Freese (a Philadelphia-based brokerage
firm) would telegraph ‘army event bandit calmly’ instead of ‘Cannot buy Canada
Southern at your limit. Please reduce limit to 23’ (Guide to Investors 1899: 385, 396). In this
artificial language, one can build sentences using the word bandit, but one
cannot build any sentence about bandits.
The new price-recording and
communication technologies required body training: investors had to be able to
observe the ticker tape uninterruptedly for hours (Wyckoff 1934: 37). Since the
stock ticker recorded and visualized minute price differences, price charts
became a new quality. A new analytical language was required in order to make
sense of price movements, a language provided by chart analysis. In its turn,
this reinforced the investor-scientist, bent on analyzing and understanding the
hidden laws of financial markets. Here is how one of the pioneers of chart
analysis defined the analyst emerging around 1900:
More and more I became
impressed with the possibilities of making money through the study of the
action of the market itself rather than the study of statistics. I wanted more
knowledge on the subject; my subscribers continued to request more light. In
many offices, active traders, more or less expert, scanned every transaction
that appeared on the tape, evidently trying to scent out coming moves. They
ignored statistics or earnings or such information, but they had great respect
for previous swings, high and low prices, and other technical
indications...Many of these traders sitting on high stools by the tickers had
no other vocation; they devoted their entire time to this business of trading
in stocks. As they became more expert, they seemed to operate a good deal on
intuition. They were especially quick to detect the starting point of new
moves, up or down, in stocks which had previously been inactive. (Wyckoff 1930:
171-2).
The
general principles promoted by investment manuals (attention, observation,
analysis) dovetailed with the categories of experience required by price-
recording technologies (permanent attention to the price flow, concentration)
and with the price charts which required a new analytical language. As Werner
De Bondt shows in Chapter 8, constant study, information, and individual effort
still rate high in the value hierarchy of contemporary investors. This does not
mean, of course, that all deal-making, market manipulation, or emotions
disappeared. Quite the contrary, but the investor-scientist distinguished
between the tumultuous surface of the market and the hidden patterns of price
movements which could be worked out through observation and analysis. In its
turn, this reinforced the idea that the market cannot be consistently beaten in
the long run and that its movements have an objective character, irreducible to
individual intentions or manipulation. According to Jean Pierre Hassoun
(Chapter 5 this volume), emotions do not disappear but become manageable. They
are seen not as determining decisions, but as instruments in building up a
personal relationship with the market.
The
separation of the science of investing from ethics allowed grand speculators
to represent themselves as strategists and planners, akin to military men, who
(aided by technology) conceive, plan, and lead battles against their opponents.
The investor Jesse Livermore, writing under the pseudonym of
Edwin Lefevre, described
the grand speculator as follows:
Back to the ticker, one
elbow leaning on the corner of the ticker-stand, tense, immobile, watching the
cascading tape intently, his soul and mind and body merged into a pair of
unblinking eyes to which every printed character was full of meaning,
surcharged with significance, eloquent in his directness. The first volley had
been fired by Dunlap; now Higgins; Willie was obeying orders; Cross and his
artillery had arrived . . . The market began to go his way. Blood was being
shed, and it was golden blood, and he was unscathed. There might be a day of
reckoning later, perhaps tomorrow; to-day there should be one—for the bulls.
He was a leader, and the unattached soldiers of fortune—the ‘traders’—gathered
under his flag and, without knowing it, fought for him, fought madly for
dollars—more dollars—even as Rock fought for railroads, more railroads... the
little ticker... sings its marvelous song of triumph and defeat in one.
(Lefevre 1907: 53)
This heroic mode of
representing grand investors is very much alive today; a fitting example is the
styling of George Soros as the man who in the early 1990s single-handedly
fought and won the battle against the Bank of England.
In the
early 1850s, parallel to the transformation of investment into a science, the
question of the relationship between investing and human nature is
reformulated. Crucial with respect to this was the distinction between ‘true’
and ‘false’ speculation made by some political thinkers and stockbrokers.
False speculation or gambling is led by excess, emotions, and lack of study.
True speculation is grounded in observation and study, conducted according to
rules, useful and honest. It is nothing else than capital put to work and ‘it
cannot be lauded and encouraged enough by all governments because it is the
veritable source of public credit’ (Regnault 1863: 103). ‘The speculator is the
pioneer of progress, he foresees, combines in advance, forecasts’ (Crampon
1863: 158). Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, one of the socialist leaders of the
nineteenth century saw speculation as a creative social force (along with
industry and trade), as an intrinsic feature of human nature and as an
expression of human freedom; all human beings are endowed with this force and
must therefore exercise it (1854: 23-5, 31). Consequently, everyone must have
the freedom and the right to speculate. The working class must get the right to
speculate too; for Proudhon, this meant abolishing the unequal access to the
stock exchange and the monopoly of stockbrokers. Other authors concurred: ‘Let
the operations of the Bourse be free, give anybody the right to auction
himself, at the auctioning hours, the commodities called stocks, bonds, public
bonds, etc.’ (Paoli 1864: 12). It also meant legalizing derivatives markets,
which in France were illegal until 1885, yet a firm presence in Paris. New York
and London made no difference in this respect.
Smaller
investors could engage with lesser sums in derivatives trading, compared with
the minimum order limits set by official stockbrokers. Consequently, the
debates about broader social access to financial markets were enmeshed with
arguments about the legality of derivatives markets.
Proudhon and his followers
(some of whom, like Henri Lefevre, were stockbrokers) saw financial
investments as a means of achieving social equality, of progress and
self-enhancement for the working classes. Some prominent British Owenite
socialists supported this argument (Thompson 1988: 158). The honest bourgeoisie
should help the working classes by participating together in joint stock
companies and hence speculating together:
Is it possible to admit
that this societal movement [toward joint stock companies], resulting not from
utopian theories but from economic necessities, and which invades all branches
of production, shall stay eternally closed to the worker? That (financial)
action is accessible only to the moneyed classes and that work will never
accede to it? Shall we believe that the commercial society, by generalizing
itself with an irresistible force, aims at reinstating a caste society, at
deepening the cleavage between the bourgeoisie and the working class, and not
at leading to the necessary and definitive fusion between these two classes,
that is, to their emancipation and triumph? In fifty years, all national
capital will be mobilized, all production values will be engaged to a social
aim; the field of individual ownership will be reduced to the objects of
consumption, or, as the [Civil] Code says, to fungible objects. Will the salary
man, this old slave, excluded since the origins of the world from ownership, be
still excluded from society, until the end of the world? In fifty years from
now, work will have the weight of capital, and the former will write off the
latter, and this will come true. (Proudhon 1854: 337)
The
argument that the stock exchange can solve tensions between social classes was
taken over by authors who saw investing as grounded in objective, scientific
rules (e.g. Lefevre 1870: v-vii). The Stock Exchange was the heart of the
social organism, recycling money in the same way the heart recycles blood (p.
243). ‘The stock exchange is the expression of public credit. The public credit
is the expression of society’s state of progress. In our era, so material and
so progressive, everything must converge toward the stock exchange. It’s like
the heart which, in a great body receives life and diffuses it throughout all
the limbs’ (Regnault 1863: 210).
Thus,
the right to invest, grounded in human nature, was presented as an argument in
struggles for widening social access to financial investments. In the late
nineteenth century United States, the fights between bucket shops and official
stockbrokers included the argument (coming from the bucket shops) that small
investors have a right to accede financial investments and that bucket shops
were fulfilling an important social function (Hochfelder 2003).
The
figure of the investor as endowed with rights has come to play a significant role
in the regulatory debates triggered by the Enron scandal (see Richard Swedberg,
Chapter 9 in this volume). The regulations concerning fair access to financial
information (like the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002) rely
on the assumption that smaller investors have a right to true information if financial markets are to allocate resources efficiently. The (information) rights of investors have to be protected as a necessary prerequisite of efficient markets (Spencer 2000: 104-5). With that, financial economics has transformed the issue of rights from a moral and legal topic into a scientific one: rights are embedded into the normative model of market efficiency.
on the assumption that smaller investors have a right to true information if financial markets are to allocate resources efficiently. The (information) rights of investors have to be protected as a necessary prerequisite of efficient markets (Spencer 2000: 104-5). With that, financial economics has transformed the issue of rights from a moral and legal topic into a scientific one: rights are embedded into the normative model of market efficiency.
Increasingly,
the political economy of the nineteenth century acknowledged financial
investments as an economic activity. Whereas for Adam Smith and other late
eighteenth century thinkers, they were situated outside the economic sphere,
political economists a century later began acknowledging financial markets as
a key social institution. The most prominent figure here is perhaps Walter
Bagehot (1874), though by far not the only one (e.g. Proudhon 1854: 31). This
recognition meant that the investor was now conceived as an economic actor
fulfilling important functions: his behavior is accounted for in terms of
rules, not of emotions or whims (see Figure 7.2). The investor keeps the market
moving, attracts capital which otherwise will
|
||||
|
||||
The
Investor: Scientist Focused person Military strategist Planner Economic man
Speculation as feature of human nature Speculation as creative social force 1 Right to speculate
Price-recording
technologies Expanding technological network Body techniques related to
attention and observation
Figure 7.2. The Field of Investing in the First Globalization Wave
Above all, it is stagnation
that we dread in the financial market, since with stagnation business is
paralyzed and values vanish. The speculation, by contrary, by its sudden
movements, its vain alarms, its failed illusions, its unexpected chances, its
alternatives of high and low, keeps financial activity going and attracts on
the stock exchange capitals which otherwise would be idle. Not only that
speculation prevents markets from being invaded by apathy, but it also helps
avoid the dangers of too high differences which menace from time to time public
fortune; because, in the time of foolish trust, speculation coldly calculates
tomorrow’s deceptions and multiplies its sales; in moments of blind panic,
speculation foresees the return to trust and doubles its acquisitions.
(Guillard 1875: 539-40).
The acknowledgment of the
investor from the left of the political spectrum does not mean that all
tensions and criticisms against investing vanish or that all political
doctrines suddenly embraced the investor. Nineteenth century US progressivism,
for instance, was a vocal critic of speculation in commodities derivatives and
of grand speculators (less so of stock markets). The field of investing was not
void of tensions; representational modes like pamphlets and satire do not
disappear. They continue to exist, but on the fringes of the field; the
investor as a fool, an insider, or a manipulator are still with us. But they
are counterbalanced by the strategist, the scientist, the planner: he who is
not a scientist and a planner is a foolish investor nowadays. In other words,
this field generates normative categories of action with respect to which other
action paths are constructed as deviant.
I have
argued that the cultural legacy of the first globalization wave consists, among
others, in the figure of the investor endowed with universal legitimacy and
validity. It relies on the interrelated, universal principles that investment
is a science and investing is grounded in rights. These principles may obscure
the fact that deceit, manipulation, and inequality in the market are still very
much with us. But they also open possibilities for action which otherwise would
not be there: witness contemporary struggles around investor rights, access to
financial information, and correct (true) information. If we would still
believe that investing is knavery, fraud, and deceit—that these are perfectly
legitimate means in financial transactions—we would accept loss of lifetime
savings in financial scandals like Enron as normal. But we do not accept it as
normal; we believe in the right to access true financial information, to study
it, to make informed decision, and to defend our rights in the marketplace. We
believe in the right to pursue in justice deviants from this norm. The cultural
legacy of the first globalization wave (universally valid knowledge and rights)
is still with us.
Investor as a Cultural Figure Notes
1. The main characteristics of
the first globalization wave are price convergence and market integration
(O’Rourke and Williamson 1999: 2, 4; Rousseau and Sylla 2001: 7). While price
convergence means a historically narrowing gap in real wages and cost of
capital between the two sides of the Atlantic, integration designates the
increasing interdependence (and reciprocal influence) of capital, production
factors, and labor markets. This means, among others, that events in one market
influence prices in other markets, and that this process gains in speed, so
that the time gap between price changes in different markets narrows too. The
first globalization wave is also characterized by social and economic
transformations which led to the territorial diffusion of investment
activities, their broader social outreach, and a considerable increase in the
number of investors. These transformations, which cannot be detailed here,
include the consolidation of the nation-state (Neal 1990), economic policy
favoring joint-stock companies (Dobbin 1994; Alborn 1998), international
migration (Wilkins 1999) and urbanization, and the rise of the news industry
(Blondheim 1994; Leyshon and Thrift 1997). Economic historians however, have
been quick to notice that factors like urbanization, international migration,
the electric telegraph, or economic policy, while important, are not enough.
As Jonathan Baskin and Paul Miranti (1997: 134) put it, market integration and
the attraction of capital from wide geographic areas presuppose ‘procedures
enabling investors to evaluate the underlying worth of traded securities’ in
the same or similar ways. These procedures imply a knowledge framework mutually
recognized and accepted over such an area: in other words, one with global
features and a potential for expansion. In this framework, financial
investments are acknowledged as socially legitimate and even desirable; moral
doubts are, for all practical purposes, suspended; social actors can make sense
of investing with respect to their personal and social lives.
沒有留言:
張貼留言